doc-src/Logics/intro.tex
author lcp
Mon, 21 Nov 1994 10:51:40 +0100
changeset 718 efca1e0710fb
parent 343 8d77f767bd26
child 3139 671a5f2cac6a
permissions -rw-r--r--
page 157 erratum
     1 %% $Id$
     2 \chapter{Basic Concepts}
     3 Several logics come with Isabelle.  Many of them are sufficiently developed
     4 to serve as comfortable reasoning environments.  They are also good
     5 starting points for defining new logics.  Each logic is distributed with
     6 sample proofs, some of which are described in this document.
     7 
     8 \begin{ttdescription}
     9 \item[\thydx{FOL}] is many-sorted first-order logic with natural
    10 deduction.  It comes in both constructive and classical versions.
    11 
    12 \item[\thydx{ZF}] is axiomatic set theory, using the Zermelo-Fraenkel
    13 axioms~\cite{suppes72}.  It is built upon classical~\FOL{}.
    14 
    15 \item[\thydx{CCL}] is Martin Coen's Classical Computational Logic,
    16   which is the basis of a preliminary method for deriving programs from
    17   proofs~\cite{coen92}.  It is built upon classical~\FOL{}.
    18  
    19 \item[\thydx{LCF}] is a version of Scott's Logic for Computable
    20   Functions, which is also implemented by the~{\sc lcf}
    21   system~\cite{paulson87}.  It is built upon classical~\FOL{}.
    22 
    23 \item[\thydx{HOL}] is the higher-order logic of Church~\cite{church40},
    24 which is also implemented by Gordon's~{\sc hol} system~\cite{mgordon-hol}.
    25 This object-logic should not be confused with Isabelle's meta-logic, which is
    26 also a form of higher-order logic.
    27 
    28 \item[\thydx{HOLCF}] is an alternative version of {\sc lcf}, defined
    29   as an extension of {\tt HOL}\@.
    30  
    31 \item[\thydx{CTT}] is a version of Martin-L\"of's Constructive Type
    32 Theory~\cite{nordstrom90}, with extensional equality.  Universes are not
    33 included.
    34  
    35 \item[\thydx{LK}] is another version of first-order logic, a classical
    36 sequent calculus.  Sequents have the form $A@1,\ldots,A@m\turn
    37 B@1,\ldots,B@n$; rules are applied using associative matching.
    38 
    39 \item[\thydx{Modal}] implements the modal logics $T$, $S4$,
    40   and~$S43$.  It is built upon~\LK{}.
    41 
    42 \item[\thydx{Cube}] is Barendregt's $\lambda$-cube.
    43 \end{ttdescription}
    44 The logics {\tt CCL}, {\tt LCF}, {\tt HOLCF}, {\tt Modal} and {\tt Cube}
    45 are currently undocumented.
    46 
    47 You should not read this before reading {\em Introduction to Isabelle\/}
    48 and performing some Isabelle proofs.  Consult the {\em Reference Manual}
    49 for more information on tactics, packages, etc.
    50 
    51 
    52 \section{Syntax definitions}
    53 The syntax of each logic is presented using a context-free grammar.
    54 These grammars obey the following conventions:
    55 \begin{itemize}
    56 \item identifiers denote nonterminal symbols
    57 \item {\tt typewriter} font denotes terminal symbols
    58 \item parentheses $(\ldots)$ express grouping
    59 \item constructs followed by a Kleene star, such as $id^*$ and $(\ldots)^*$
    60 can be repeated~0 or more times 
    61 \item alternatives are separated by a vertical bar,~$|$
    62 \item the symbol for alphanumeric identifiers is~{\it id\/} 
    63 \item the symbol for scheme variables is~{\it var}
    64 \end{itemize}
    65 To reduce the number of nonterminals and grammar rules required, Isabelle's
    66 syntax module employs {\bf priorities},\index{priorities} or precedences.
    67 Each grammar rule is given by a mixfix declaration, which has a priority,
    68 and each argument place has a priority.  This general approach handles
    69 infix operators that associate either to the left or to the right, as well
    70 as prefix and binding operators.
    71 
    72 In a syntactically valid expression, an operator's arguments never involve
    73 an operator of lower priority unless brackets are used.  Consider
    74 first-order logic, where $\exists$ has lower priority than $\disj$,
    75 which has lower priority than $\conj$.  There, $P\conj Q \disj R$
    76 abbreviates $(P\conj Q) \disj R$ rather than $P\conj (Q\disj R)$.  Also,
    77 $\exists x.P\disj Q$ abbreviates $\exists x.(P\disj Q)$ rather than
    78 $(\exists x.P)\disj Q$.  Note especially that $P\disj(\exists x.Q)$
    79 becomes syntactically invalid if the brackets are removed.
    80 
    81 A {\bf binder} is a symbol associated with a constant of type
    82 $(\sigma\To\tau)\To\tau'$.  For instance, we may declare~$\forall$ as a
    83 binder for the constant~$All$, which has type $(\alpha\To o)\To o$.  This
    84 defines the syntax $\forall x.t$ to mean $All(\lambda x.t)$.  We can
    85 also write $\forall x@1\ldots x@m.t$ to abbreviate $\forall x@1.  \ldots
    86 \forall x@m.t$; this is possible for any constant provided that $\tau$ and
    87 $\tau'$ are the same type.  \HOL's description operator $\epsilon x.P(x)$
    88 has type $(\alpha\To bool)\To\alpha$ and can bind only one variable, except
    89 when $\alpha$ is $bool$.  \ZF's bounded quantifier $\forall x\in A.P(x)$
    90 cannot be declared as a binder because it has type $[i, i\To o]\To o$.  The
    91 syntax for binders allows type constraints on bound variables, as in
    92 \[ \forall (x{::}\alpha) \; (y{::}\beta). R(x,y) \]
    93 
    94 To avoid excess detail, the logic descriptions adopt a semi-formal style.
    95 Infix operators and binding operators are listed in separate tables, which
    96 include their priorities.  Grammar descriptions do not include numeric
    97 priorities; instead, the rules appear in order of decreasing priority.
    98 This should suffice for most purposes; for full details, please consult the
    99 actual syntax definitions in the {\tt.thy} files.
   100 
   101 Each nonterminal symbol is associated with some Isabelle type.  For
   102 example, the formulae of first-order logic have type~$o$.  Every
   103 Isabelle expression of type~$o$ is therefore a formula.  These include
   104 atomic formulae such as $P$, where $P$ is a variable of type~$o$, and more
   105 generally expressions such as $P(t,u)$, where $P$, $t$ and~$u$ have
   106 suitable types.  Therefore, `expression of type~$o$' is listed as a
   107 separate possibility in the grammar for formulae.
   108 
   109 
   110 \section{Proof procedures}\label{sec:safe}
   111 Most object-logics come with simple proof procedures.  These are reasonably
   112 powerful for interactive use, though often simplistic and incomplete.  You
   113 can do single-step proofs using \verb|resolve_tac| and
   114 \verb|assume_tac|, referring to the inference rules of the logic by {\sc
   115 ml} identifiers.
   116 
   117 For theorem proving, rules can be classified as {\bf safe} or {\bf unsafe}.
   118 A rule is safe if applying it to a provable goal always yields provable
   119 subgoals.  If a rule is safe then it can be applied automatically to a goal
   120 without destroying our chances of finding a proof.  For instance, all the
   121 rules of the classical sequent calculus {\sc lk} are safe.  Universal
   122 elimination is unsafe if the formula $\all{x}P(x)$ is deleted after use.
   123 Other unsafe rules include the following:
   124 \[ \infer[({\disj}I1)]{P\disj Q}{P} \qquad 
   125    \infer[({\imp}E)]{Q}{P\imp Q & P} \qquad
   126    \infer[({\exists}I)]{\exists x.P}{P[t/x]} 
   127 \]
   128 
   129 Proof procedures use safe rules whenever possible, delaying the application
   130 of unsafe rules. Those safe rules are preferred that generate the fewest
   131 subgoals. Safe rules are (by definition) deterministic, while the unsafe
   132 rules require search. The design of a suitable set of rules can be as
   133 important as the strategy for applying them.
   134 
   135 Many of the proof procedures use backtracking.  Typically they attempt to
   136 solve subgoal~$i$ by repeatedly applying a certain tactic to it.  This
   137 tactic, which is known as a {\bf step tactic}, resolves a selection of
   138 rules with subgoal~$i$. This may replace one subgoal by many;  the
   139 search persists until there are fewer subgoals in total than at the start.
   140 Backtracking happens when the search reaches a dead end: when the step
   141 tactic fails.  Alternative outcomes are then searched by a depth-first or
   142 best-first strategy.