doc-src/Ref/classical.tex
author wenzelm
Fri, 20 May 2011 14:03:42 +0200
changeset 43760 e87888b4152f
parent 30184 37969710e61f
child 44131 c40adab7568e
permissions -rw-r--r--
removed some obsolete text;
     1 
     2 \chapter{The Classical Reasoner}\label{chap:classical}
     3 \index{classical reasoner|(}
     4 \newcommand\ainfer[2]{\begin{array}{r@{\,}l}#2\\ \hline#1\end{array}}
     5 
     6 Although Isabelle is generic, many users will be working in some extension of
     7 classical first-order logic.  Isabelle's set theory~ZF is built upon
     8 theory~FOL, while HOL conceptually contains first-order logic as a fragment.
     9 Theorem-proving in predicate logic is undecidable, but many researchers have
    10 developed strategies to assist in this task.
    11 
    12 Isabelle's classical reasoner is an \ML{} functor that accepts certain
    13 information about a logic and delivers a suite of automatic tactics.  Each
    14 tactic takes a collection of rules and executes a simple, non-clausal proof
    15 procedure.  They are slow and simplistic compared with resolution theorem
    16 provers, but they can save considerable time and effort.  They can prove
    17 theorems such as Pelletier's~\cite{pelletier86} problems~40 and~41 in
    18 seconds:
    19 \[ (\exists y. \forall x. J(y,x) \bimp \neg J(x,x))  
    20    \imp  \neg (\forall x. \exists y. \forall z. J(z,y) \bimp \neg J(z,x)) \]
    21 \[ (\forall z. \exists y. \forall x. F(x,y) \bimp F(x,z) \conj \neg F(x,x))
    22    \imp \neg (\exists z. \forall x. F(x,z))  
    23 \]
    24 %
    25 The tactics are generic.  They are not restricted to first-order logic, and
    26 have been heavily used in the development of Isabelle's set theory.  Few
    27 interactive proof assistants provide this much automation.  The tactics can
    28 be traced, and their components can be called directly; in this manner,
    29 any proof can be viewed interactively.
    30 
    31 We shall first discuss the underlying principles, then present the classical
    32 reasoner.  Finally, we shall see how to instantiate it for new logics.  The
    33 logics FOL, ZF, HOL and HOLCF have it already installed.
    34 
    35 
    36 \section{The sequent calculus}
    37 \index{sequent calculus}
    38 Isabelle supports natural deduction, which is easy to use for interactive
    39 proof.  But natural deduction does not easily lend itself to automation,
    40 and has a bias towards intuitionism.  For certain proofs in classical
    41 logic, it can not be called natural.  The {\bf sequent calculus}, a
    42 generalization of natural deduction, is easier to automate.
    43 
    44 A {\bf sequent} has the form $\Gamma\turn\Delta$, where $\Gamma$
    45 and~$\Delta$ are sets of formulae.%
    46 \footnote{For first-order logic, sequents can equivalently be made from
    47   lists or multisets of formulae.} The sequent
    48 \[ P@1,\ldots,P@m\turn Q@1,\ldots,Q@n \]
    49 is {\bf valid} if $P@1\conj\ldots\conj P@m$ implies $Q@1\disj\ldots\disj
    50 Q@n$.  Thus $P@1,\ldots,P@m$ represent assumptions, each of which is true,
    51 while $Q@1,\ldots,Q@n$ represent alternative goals.  A sequent is {\bf
    52 basic} if its left and right sides have a common formula, as in $P,Q\turn
    53 Q,R$; basic sequents are trivially valid.
    54 
    55 Sequent rules are classified as {\bf right} or {\bf left}, indicating which
    56 side of the $\turn$~symbol they operate on.  Rules that operate on the
    57 right side are analogous to natural deduction's introduction rules, and
    58 left rules are analogous to elimination rules.  
    59 Recall the natural deduction rules for
    60   first-order logic, 
    61 \iflabelundefined{fol-fig}{from {\it Introduction to Isabelle}}%
    62                           {Fig.\ts\ref{fol-fig}}.
    63 The sequent calculus analogue of~$({\imp}I)$ is the rule
    64 $$
    65 \ainfer{\Gamma &\turn \Delta, P\imp Q}{P,\Gamma &\turn \Delta,Q}
    66 \eqno({\imp}R)
    67 $$
    68 This breaks down some implication on the right side of a sequent; $\Gamma$
    69 and $\Delta$ stand for the sets of formulae that are unaffected by the
    70 inference.  The analogue of the pair~$({\disj}I1)$ and~$({\disj}I2)$ is the
    71 single rule 
    72 $$
    73 \ainfer{\Gamma &\turn \Delta, P\disj Q}{\Gamma &\turn \Delta,P,Q}
    74 \eqno({\disj}R)
    75 $$
    76 This breaks down some disjunction on the right side, replacing it by both
    77 disjuncts.  Thus, the sequent calculus is a kind of multiple-conclusion logic.
    78 
    79 To illustrate the use of multiple formulae on the right, let us prove
    80 the classical theorem $(P\imp Q)\disj(Q\imp P)$.  Working backwards, we
    81 reduce this formula to a basic sequent:
    82 \[ \infer[(\disj)R]{\turn(P\imp Q)\disj(Q\imp P)}
    83    {\infer[(\imp)R]{\turn(P\imp Q), (Q\imp P)\;}
    84     {\infer[(\imp)R]{P \turn Q, (Q\imp P)\qquad}
    85                     {P, Q \turn Q, P\qquad\qquad}}}
    86 \]
    87 This example is typical of the sequent calculus: start with the desired
    88 theorem and apply rules backwards in a fairly arbitrary manner.  This yields a
    89 surprisingly effective proof procedure.  Quantifiers add few complications,
    90 since Isabelle handles parameters and schematic variables.  See Chapter~10
    91 of {\em ML for the Working Programmer}~\cite{paulson-ml2} for further
    92 discussion.
    93 
    94 
    95 \section{Simulating sequents by natural deduction}
    96 Isabelle can represent sequents directly, as in the object-logic~\texttt{LK}\@.
    97 But natural deduction is easier to work with, and most object-logics employ
    98 it.  Fortunately, we can simulate the sequent $P@1,\ldots,P@m\turn
    99 Q@1,\ldots,Q@n$ by the Isabelle formula
   100 \[ \List{P@1;\ldots;P@m; \neg Q@2;\ldots; \neg Q@n}\Imp Q@1, \]
   101 where the order of the assumptions and the choice of~$Q@1$ are arbitrary.
   102 Elim-resolution plays a key role in simulating sequent proofs.
   103 
   104 We can easily handle reasoning on the left.
   105 As discussed in
   106 \iflabelundefined{destruct}{{\it Introduction to Isabelle}}{{\S}\ref{destruct}}, 
   107 elim-resolution with the rules $(\disj E)$, $(\bot E)$ and $(\exists E)$
   108 achieves a similar effect as the corresponding sequent rules.  For the
   109 other connectives, we use sequent-style elimination rules instead of
   110 destruction rules such as $({\conj}E1,2)$ and $(\forall E)$.  But note that
   111 the rule $(\neg L)$ has no effect under our representation of sequents!
   112 $$
   113 \ainfer{\neg P,\Gamma &\turn \Delta}{\Gamma &\turn \Delta,P}\eqno({\neg}L)
   114 $$
   115 What about reasoning on the right?  Introduction rules can only affect the
   116 formula in the conclusion, namely~$Q@1$.  The other right-side formulae are
   117 represented as negated assumptions, $\neg Q@2$, \ldots,~$\neg Q@n$.  
   118 \index{assumptions!negated}
   119 In order to operate on one of these, it must first be exchanged with~$Q@1$.
   120 Elim-resolution with the {\bf swap} rule has this effect:
   121 $$ \List{\neg P; \; \neg R\Imp P} \Imp R   \eqno(swap)  $$
   122 To ensure that swaps occur only when necessary, each introduction rule is
   123 converted into a swapped form: it is resolved with the second premise
   124 of~$(swap)$.  The swapped form of~$({\conj}I)$, which might be
   125 called~$({\neg\conj}E)$, is
   126 \[ \List{\neg(P\conj Q); \; \neg R\Imp P; \; \neg R\Imp Q} \Imp R. \]
   127 Similarly, the swapped form of~$({\imp}I)$ is
   128 \[ \List{\neg(P\imp Q); \; \List{\neg R;P}\Imp Q} \Imp R  \]
   129 Swapped introduction rules are applied using elim-resolution, which deletes
   130 the negated formula.  Our representation of sequents also requires the use
   131 of ordinary introduction rules.  If we had no regard for readability, we
   132 could treat the right side more uniformly by representing sequents as
   133 \[ \List{P@1;\ldots;P@m; \neg Q@1;\ldots; \neg Q@n}\Imp \bot. \]
   134 
   135 
   136 \section{Extra rules for the sequent calculus}
   137 As mentioned, destruction rules such as $({\conj}E1,2)$ and $(\forall E)$
   138 must be replaced by sequent-style elimination rules.  In addition, we need
   139 rules to embody the classical equivalence between $P\imp Q$ and $\neg P\disj
   140 Q$.  The introduction rules~$({\disj}I1,2)$ are replaced by a rule that
   141 simulates $({\disj}R)$:
   142 \[ (\neg Q\Imp P) \Imp P\disj Q \]
   143 The destruction rule $({\imp}E)$ is replaced by
   144 \[ \List{P\imp Q;\; \neg P\Imp R;\; Q\Imp R} \Imp R. \]
   145 Quantifier replication also requires special rules.  In classical logic,
   146 $\exists x{.}P$ is equivalent to $\neg\forall x{.}\neg P$; the rules
   147 $(\exists R)$ and $(\forall L)$ are dual:
   148 \[ \ainfer{\Gamma &\turn \Delta, \exists x{.}P}
   149           {\Gamma &\turn \Delta, \exists x{.}P, P[t/x]} \; (\exists R)
   150    \qquad
   151    \ainfer{\forall x{.}P, \Gamma &\turn \Delta}
   152           {P[t/x], \forall x{.}P, \Gamma &\turn \Delta} \; (\forall L)
   153 \]
   154 Thus both kinds of quantifier may be replicated.  Theorems requiring
   155 multiple uses of a universal formula are easy to invent; consider 
   156 \[ (\forall x.P(x)\imp P(f(x))) \conj P(a) \imp P(f^n(a)), \]
   157 for any~$n>1$.  Natural examples of the multiple use of an existential
   158 formula are rare; a standard one is $\exists x.\forall y. P(x)\imp P(y)$.
   159 
   160 Forgoing quantifier replication loses completeness, but gains decidability,
   161 since the search space becomes finite.  Many useful theorems can be proved
   162 without replication, and the search generally delivers its verdict in a
   163 reasonable time.  To adopt this approach, represent the sequent rules
   164 $(\exists R)$, $(\exists L)$ and $(\forall R)$ by $(\exists I)$, $(\exists
   165 E)$ and $(\forall I)$, respectively, and put $(\forall E)$ into elimination
   166 form:
   167 $$ \List{\forall x{.}P(x); P(t)\Imp Q} \Imp Q    \eqno(\forall E@2) $$
   168 Elim-resolution with this rule will delete the universal formula after a
   169 single use.  To replicate universal quantifiers, replace the rule by
   170 $$
   171 \List{\forall x{.}P(x);\; \List{P(t); \forall x{.}P(x)}\Imp Q} \Imp Q.
   172 \eqno(\forall E@3)
   173 $$
   174 To replicate existential quantifiers, replace $(\exists I)$ by
   175 \[ \List{\neg(\exists x{.}P(x)) \Imp P(t)} \Imp \exists x{.}P(x). \]
   176 All introduction rules mentioned above are also useful in swapped form.
   177 
   178 Replication makes the search space infinite; we must apply the rules with
   179 care.  The classical reasoner distinguishes between safe and unsafe
   180 rules, applying the latter only when there is no alternative.  Depth-first
   181 search may well go down a blind alley; best-first search is better behaved
   182 in an infinite search space.  However, quantifier replication is too
   183 expensive to prove any but the simplest theorems.
   184 
   185 
   186 \section{Classical rule sets}
   187 \index{classical sets}
   188 Each automatic tactic takes a {\bf classical set} --- a collection of
   189 rules, classified as introduction or elimination and as {\bf safe} or {\bf
   190 unsafe}.  In general, safe rules can be attempted blindly, while unsafe
   191 rules must be used with care.  A safe rule must never reduce a provable
   192 goal to an unprovable set of subgoals.  
   193 
   194 The rule~$({\disj}I1)$ is unsafe because it reduces $P\disj Q$ to~$P$.  Any
   195 rule is unsafe whose premises contain new unknowns.  The elimination
   196 rule~$(\forall E@2)$ is unsafe, since it is applied via elim-resolution,
   197 which discards the assumption $\forall x{.}P(x)$ and replaces it by the
   198 weaker assumption~$P(\Var{t})$.  The rule $({\exists}I)$ is unsafe for
   199 similar reasons.  The rule~$(\forall E@3)$ is unsafe in a different sense:
   200 since it keeps the assumption $\forall x{.}P(x)$, it is prone to looping.
   201 In classical first-order logic, all rules are safe except those mentioned
   202 above.
   203 
   204 The safe/unsafe distinction is vague, and may be regarded merely as a way
   205 of giving some rules priority over others.  One could argue that
   206 $({\disj}E)$ is unsafe, because repeated application of it could generate
   207 exponentially many subgoals.  Induction rules are unsafe because inductive
   208 proofs are difficult to set up automatically.  Any inference is unsafe that
   209 instantiates an unknown in the proof state --- thus \ttindex{match_tac}
   210 must be used, rather than \ttindex{resolve_tac}.  Even proof by assumption
   211 is unsafe if it instantiates unknowns shared with other subgoals --- thus
   212 \ttindex{eq_assume_tac} must be used, rather than \ttindex{assume_tac}.
   213 
   214 \subsection{Adding rules to classical sets}
   215 Classical rule sets belong to the abstract type \mltydx{claset}, which
   216 supports the following operations (provided the classical reasoner is
   217 installed!):
   218 \begin{ttbox} 
   219 empty_cs : claset
   220 print_cs : claset -> unit
   221 rep_cs : claset -> \{safeEs: thm list, safeIs: thm list,
   222                     hazEs: thm list,  hazIs: thm list, 
   223                     swrappers: (string * wrapper) list, 
   224                     uwrappers: (string * wrapper) list,
   225                     safe0_netpair: netpair, safep_netpair: netpair,
   226                     haz_netpair: netpair, dup_netpair: netpair\}
   227 addSIs   : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   228 addSEs   : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   229 addSDs   : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   230 addIs    : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   231 addEs    : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   232 addDs    : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   233 delrules : claset * thm list -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   234 \end{ttbox}
   235 The add operations ignore any rule already present in the claset with the same
   236 classification (such as safe introduction).  They print a warning if the rule
   237 has already been added with some other classification, but add the rule
   238 anyway.  Calling \texttt{delrules} deletes all occurrences of a rule from the
   239 claset, but see the warning below concerning destruction rules.
   240 \begin{ttdescription}
   241 \item[\ttindexbold{empty_cs}] is the empty classical set.
   242 
   243 \item[\ttindexbold{print_cs} $cs$] displays the printable contents of~$cs$,
   244   which is the rules. All other parts are non-printable.
   245 
   246 \item[\ttindexbold{rep_cs} $cs$] decomposes $cs$ as a record of its internal 
   247   components, namely the safe introduction and elimination rules, the unsafe
   248   introduction and elimination rules, the lists of safe and unsafe wrappers
   249   (see \ref{sec:modifying-search}), and the internalized forms of the rules.
   250 
   251 \item[$cs$ addSIs $rules$] \indexbold{*addSIs}
   252 adds safe introduction~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   253 
   254 \item[$cs$ addSEs $rules$] \indexbold{*addSEs}
   255 adds safe elimination~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   256 
   257 \item[$cs$ addSDs $rules$] \indexbold{*addSDs}
   258 adds safe destruction~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   259 
   260 \item[$cs$ addIs $rules$] \indexbold{*addIs}
   261 adds unsafe introduction~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   262 
   263 \item[$cs$ addEs $rules$] \indexbold{*addEs}
   264 adds unsafe elimination~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   265 
   266 \item[$cs$ addDs $rules$] \indexbold{*addDs}
   267 adds unsafe destruction~$rules$ to~$cs$.
   268 
   269 \item[$cs$ delrules $rules$] \indexbold{*delrules}
   270 deletes~$rules$ from~$cs$.  It prints a warning for those rules that are not
   271 in~$cs$.
   272 \end{ttdescription}
   273 
   274 \begin{warn}
   275   If you added $rule$ using \texttt{addSDs} or \texttt{addDs}, then you must delete
   276   it as follows:
   277 \begin{ttbox}
   278 \(cs\) delrules [make_elim \(rule\)]
   279 \end{ttbox}
   280 \par\noindent
   281 This is necessary because the operators \texttt{addSDs} and \texttt{addDs} convert
   282 the destruction rules to elimination rules by applying \ttindex{make_elim},
   283 and then insert them using \texttt{addSEs} and \texttt{addEs}, respectively.
   284 \end{warn}
   285 
   286 Introduction rules are those that can be applied using ordinary resolution.
   287 The classical set automatically generates their swapped forms, which will
   288 be applied using elim-resolution.  Elimination rules are applied using
   289 elim-resolution.  In a classical set, rules are sorted by the number of new
   290 subgoals they will yield; rules that generate the fewest subgoals will be
   291 tried first (see {\S}\ref{biresolve_tac}).
   292 
   293 For elimination and destruction rules there are variants of the add operations
   294 adding a rule in a way such that it is applied only if also its second premise
   295 can be unified with an assumption of the current proof state:
   296 \indexbold{*addSE2}\indexbold{*addSD2}\indexbold{*addE2}\indexbold{*addD2}
   297 \begin{ttbox}
   298 addSE2      : claset * (string * thm) -> claset           \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   299 addSD2      : claset * (string * thm) -> claset           \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   300 addE2       : claset * (string * thm) -> claset           \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   301 addD2       : claset * (string * thm) -> claset           \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   302 \end{ttbox}
   303 \begin{warn}
   304   A rule to be added in this special way must be given a name, which is used 
   305   to delete it again -- when desired -- using \texttt{delSWrappers} or 
   306   \texttt{delWrappers}, respectively. This is because these add operations
   307   are implemented as wrappers (see \ref{sec:modifying-search} below).
   308 \end{warn}
   309 
   310 
   311 \subsection{Modifying the search step}
   312 \label{sec:modifying-search}
   313 For a given classical set, the proof strategy is simple.  Perform as many safe
   314 inferences as possible; or else, apply certain safe rules, allowing
   315 instantiation of unknowns; or else, apply an unsafe rule.  The tactics also
   316 eliminate assumptions of the form $x=t$ by substitution if they have been set
   317 up to do so (see \texttt{hyp_subst_tacs} in~{\S}\ref{sec:classical-setup} below).
   318 They may perform a form of Modus Ponens: if there are assumptions $P\imp Q$
   319 and~$P$, then replace $P\imp Q$ by~$Q$.
   320 
   321 The classical reasoning tactics --- except \texttt{blast_tac}! --- allow
   322 you to modify this basic proof strategy by applying two lists of arbitrary 
   323 {\bf wrapper tacticals} to it. 
   324 The first wrapper list, which is considered to contain safe wrappers only, 
   325 affects \ttindex{safe_step_tac} and all the tactics that call it.  
   326 The second one, which may contain unsafe wrappers, affects the unsafe parts
   327 of \ttindex{step_tac}, \ttindex{slow_step_tac}, and the tactics that call them.
   328 A wrapper transforms each step of the search, for example 
   329 by attempting other tactics before or after the original step tactic. 
   330 All members of a wrapper list are applied in turn to the respective step tactic.
   331 
   332 Initially the two wrapper lists are empty, which means no modification of the
   333 step tactics. Safe and unsafe wrappers are added to a claset 
   334 with the functions given below, supplying them with wrapper names. 
   335 These names may be used to selectively delete wrappers.
   336 
   337 \begin{ttbox} 
   338 type wrapper = (int -> tactic) -> (int -> tactic);
   339 
   340 addSWrapper  : claset * (string *  wrapper       ) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   341 addSbefore   : claset * (string * (int -> tactic)) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   342 addSafter    : claset * (string * (int -> tactic)) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   343 delSWrapper  : claset *  string                    -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   344 
   345 addWrapper   : claset * (string *  wrapper       ) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   346 addbefore    : claset * (string * (int -> tactic)) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   347 addafter     : claset * (string * (int -> tactic)) -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   348 delWrapper   : claset *  string                    -> claset \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   349 
   350 addSss       : claset * simpset -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   351 addss        : claset * simpset -> claset                 \hfill{\bf infix 4}
   352 \end{ttbox}
   353 %
   354 
   355 \begin{ttdescription}
   356 \item[$cs$ addSWrapper $(name,wrapper)$] \indexbold{*addSWrapper}
   357 adds a new wrapper, which should yield a safe tactic, 
   358 to modify the existing safe step tactic.
   359 
   360 \item[$cs$ addSbefore $(name,tac)$] \indexbold{*addSbefore}
   361 adds the given tactic as a safe wrapper, such that it is tried 
   362 {\em before} each safe step of the search.
   363 
   364 \item[$cs$ addSafter $(name,tac)$] \indexbold{*addSafter}
   365 adds the given tactic as a safe wrapper, such that it is tried 
   366 when a safe step of the search would fail.
   367 
   368 \item[$cs$ delSWrapper $name$] \indexbold{*delSWrapper}
   369 deletes the safe wrapper with the given name.
   370 
   371 \item[$cs$ addWrapper $(name,wrapper)$] \indexbold{*addWrapper}
   372 adds a new wrapper to modify the existing (unsafe) step tactic.
   373 
   374 \item[$cs$ addbefore $(name,tac)$] \indexbold{*addbefore}
   375 adds the given tactic as an unsafe wrapper, such that it its result is 
   376 concatenated {\em before} the result of each unsafe step.
   377 
   378 \item[$cs$ addafter $(name,tac)$] \indexbold{*addafter}
   379 adds the given tactic as an unsafe wrapper, such that it its result is 
   380 concatenated {\em after} the result of each unsafe step.
   381 
   382 \item[$cs$ delWrapper $name$] \indexbold{*delWrapper}
   383 deletes the unsafe wrapper with the given name.
   384 
   385 \item[$cs$ addSss $ss$] \indexbold{*addss}
   386 adds the simpset~$ss$ to the classical set.  The assumptions and goal will be
   387 simplified, in a rather safe way, after each safe step of the search.
   388 
   389 \item[$cs$ addss $ss$] \indexbold{*addss}
   390 adds the simpset~$ss$ to the classical set.  The assumptions and goal will be
   391 simplified, before the each unsafe step of the search.
   392 
   393 \end{ttdescription}
   394 
   395 \index{simplification!from classical reasoner} 
   396 Strictly speaking, the operators \texttt{addss} and \texttt{addSss}
   397 are not part of the classical reasoner.
   398 , which are used as primitives 
   399 for the automatic tactics described in {\S}\ref{sec:automatic-tactics}, are
   400 implemented as wrapper tacticals.
   401 they  
   402 \begin{warn}
   403 Being defined as wrappers, these operators are inappropriate for adding more 
   404 than one simpset at a time: the simpset added last overwrites any earlier ones.
   405 When a simpset combined with a claset is to be augmented, this should done 
   406 {\em before} combining it with the claset.
   407 \end{warn}
   408 
   409 
   410 \section{The classical tactics}
   411 \index{classical reasoner!tactics} If installed, the classical module provides
   412 powerful theorem-proving tactics.
   413 
   414 
   415 \subsection{The tableau prover}
   416 The tactic \texttt{blast_tac} searches for a proof using a fast tableau prover,
   417 coded directly in \ML.  It then reconstructs the proof using Isabelle
   418 tactics.  It is faster and more powerful than the other classical
   419 reasoning tactics, but has major limitations too.
   420 \begin{itemize}
   421 \item It does not use the wrapper tacticals described above, such as
   422   \ttindex{addss}.
   423 \item It does not perform higher-order unification, as needed by the rule {\tt
   424     rangeI} in HOL and \texttt{RepFunI} in ZF.  There are often alternatives
   425   to such rules, for example {\tt range_eqI} and \texttt{RepFun_eqI}.
   426 \item Function variables may only be applied to parameters of the subgoal.
   427 (This restriction arises because the prover does not use higher-order
   428 unification.)  If other function variables are present then the prover will
   429 fail with the message {\small\tt Function Var's argument not a bound variable}.
   430 \item Its proof strategy is more general than \texttt{fast_tac}'s but can be
   431   slower.  If \texttt{blast_tac} fails or seems to be running forever, try {\tt
   432   fast_tac} and the other tactics described below.
   433 \end{itemize}
   434 %
   435 \begin{ttbox} 
   436 blast_tac        : claset -> int -> tactic
   437 Blast.depth_tac  : claset -> int -> int -> tactic
   438 Blast.trace      : bool ref \hfill{\bf initially false}
   439 \end{ttbox}
   440 The two tactics differ on how they bound the number of unsafe steps used in a
   441 proof.  While \texttt{blast_tac} starts with a bound of zero and increases it
   442 successively to~20, \texttt{Blast.depth_tac} applies a user-supplied search bound.
   443 \begin{ttdescription}
   444 \item[\ttindexbold{blast_tac} $cs$ $i$] tries to prove
   445   subgoal~$i$, increasing the search bound using iterative
   446   deepening~\cite{korf85}. 
   447   
   448 \item[\ttindexbold{Blast.depth_tac} $cs$ $lim$ $i$] tries
   449   to prove subgoal~$i$ using a search bound of $lim$.  Sometimes a slow
   450   proof using \texttt{blast_tac} can be made much faster by supplying the
   451   successful search bound to this tactic instead.
   452   
   453 \item[set \ttindexbold{Blast.trace};] \index{tracing!of classical prover}
   454   causes the tableau prover to print a trace of its search.  At each step it
   455   displays the formula currently being examined and reports whether the branch
   456   has been closed, extended or split.
   457 \end{ttdescription}
   458 
   459 
   460 \subsection{Automatic tactics}\label{sec:automatic-tactics}
   461 \begin{ttbox} 
   462 type clasimpset = claset * simpset;
   463 auto_tac        : clasimpset ->        tactic
   464 force_tac       : clasimpset -> int -> tactic
   465 auto            : unit -> unit
   466 force           : int  -> unit
   467 \end{ttbox}
   468 The automatic tactics attempt to prove goals using a combination of
   469 simplification and classical reasoning. 
   470 \begin{ttdescription}
   471 \item[\ttindexbold{auto_tac $(cs,ss)$}] is intended for situations where 
   472 there are a lot of mostly trivial subgoals; it proves all the easy ones, 
   473 leaving the ones it cannot prove.
   474 (Unfortunately, attempting to prove the hard ones may take a long time.)  
   475 \item[\ttindexbold{force_tac} $(cs,ss)$ $i$] is intended to prove subgoal~$i$ 
   476 completely. It tries to apply all fancy tactics it knows about, 
   477 performing a rather exhaustive search.
   478 \end{ttdescription}
   479 
   480 
   481 \subsection{Semi-automatic tactics}
   482 \begin{ttbox} 
   483 clarify_tac      : claset -> int -> tactic
   484 clarify_step_tac : claset -> int -> tactic
   485 clarsimp_tac     : clasimpset -> int -> tactic
   486 \end{ttbox}
   487 Use these when the automatic tactics fail.  They perform all the obvious
   488 logical inferences that do not split the subgoal.  The result is a
   489 simpler subgoal that can be tackled by other means, such as by
   490 instantiating quantifiers yourself.
   491 \begin{ttdescription}
   492 \item[\ttindexbold{clarify_tac} $cs$ $i$] performs a series of safe steps on
   493 subgoal~$i$ by repeatedly calling \texttt{clarify_step_tac}.
   494 \item[\ttindexbold{clarify_step_tac} $cs$ $i$] performs a safe step on
   495   subgoal~$i$.  No splitting step is applied; for example, the subgoal $A\conj
   496   B$ is left as a conjunction.  Proof by assumption, Modus Ponens, etc., may be
   497   performed provided they do not instantiate unknowns.  Assumptions of the
   498   form $x=t$ may be eliminated.  The user-supplied safe wrapper tactical is
   499   applied.
   500 \item[\ttindexbold{clarsimp_tac} $cs$ $i$] acts like \texttt{clarify_tac}, but
   501 also does simplification with the given simpset. Note that if the simpset 
   502 includes a splitter for the premises, the subgoal may still be split.
   503 \end{ttdescription}
   504 
   505 
   506 \subsection{Other classical tactics}
   507 \begin{ttbox} 
   508 fast_tac      : claset -> int -> tactic
   509 best_tac      : claset -> int -> tactic
   510 slow_tac      : claset -> int -> tactic
   511 slow_best_tac : claset -> int -> tactic
   512 \end{ttbox}
   513 These tactics attempt to prove a subgoal using sequent-style reasoning.
   514 Unlike \texttt{blast_tac}, they construct proofs directly in Isabelle.  Their
   515 effect is restricted (by \texttt{SELECT_GOAL}) to one subgoal; they either prove
   516 this subgoal or fail.  The \texttt{slow_} versions conduct a broader
   517 search.%
   518 \footnote{They may, when backtracking from a failed proof attempt, undo even
   519   the step of proving a subgoal by assumption.}
   520 
   521 The best-first tactics are guided by a heuristic function: typically, the
   522 total size of the proof state.  This function is supplied in the functor call
   523 that sets up the classical reasoner.
   524 \begin{ttdescription}
   525 \item[\ttindexbold{fast_tac} $cs$ $i$] applies \texttt{step_tac} using
   526 depth-first search to prove subgoal~$i$.
   527 
   528 \item[\ttindexbold{best_tac} $cs$ $i$] applies \texttt{step_tac} using
   529 best-first search to prove subgoal~$i$.
   530 
   531 \item[\ttindexbold{slow_tac} $cs$ $i$] applies \texttt{slow_step_tac} using
   532 depth-first search to prove subgoal~$i$.
   533 
   534 \item[\ttindexbold{slow_best_tac} $cs$ $i$] applies \texttt{slow_step_tac} with
   535 best-first search to prove subgoal~$i$.
   536 \end{ttdescription}
   537 
   538 
   539 \subsection{Depth-limited automatic tactics}
   540 \begin{ttbox} 
   541 depth_tac  : claset -> int -> int -> tactic
   542 deepen_tac : claset -> int -> int -> tactic
   543 \end{ttbox}
   544 These work by exhaustive search up to a specified depth.  Unsafe rules are
   545 modified to preserve the formula they act on, so that it be used repeatedly.
   546 They can prove more goals than \texttt{fast_tac} can but are much
   547 slower, for example if the assumptions have many universal quantifiers.
   548 
   549 The depth limits the number of unsafe steps.  If you can estimate the minimum
   550 number of unsafe steps needed, supply this value as~$m$ to save time.
   551 \begin{ttdescription}
   552 \item[\ttindexbold{depth_tac} $cs$ $m$ $i$] 
   553 tries to prove subgoal~$i$ by exhaustive search up to depth~$m$.
   554 
   555 \item[\ttindexbold{deepen_tac} $cs$ $m$ $i$] 
   556 tries to prove subgoal~$i$ by iterative deepening.  It calls \texttt{depth_tac}
   557 repeatedly with increasing depths, starting with~$m$.
   558 \end{ttdescription}
   559 
   560 
   561 \subsection{Single-step tactics}
   562 \begin{ttbox} 
   563 safe_step_tac : claset -> int -> tactic
   564 safe_tac      : claset        -> tactic
   565 inst_step_tac : claset -> int -> tactic
   566 step_tac      : claset -> int -> tactic
   567 slow_step_tac : claset -> int -> tactic
   568 \end{ttbox}
   569 The automatic proof procedures call these tactics.  By calling them
   570 yourself, you can execute these procedures one step at a time.
   571 \begin{ttdescription}
   572 \item[\ttindexbold{safe_step_tac} $cs$ $i$] performs a safe step on
   573   subgoal~$i$.  The safe wrapper tacticals are applied to a tactic that may
   574   include proof by assumption or Modus Ponens (taking care not to instantiate
   575   unknowns), or substitution.
   576 
   577 \item[\ttindexbold{safe_tac} $cs$] repeatedly performs safe steps on all 
   578 subgoals.  It is deterministic, with at most one outcome.  
   579 
   580 \item[\ttindexbold{inst_step_tac} $cs$ $i$] is like \texttt{safe_step_tac},
   581 but allows unknowns to be instantiated.
   582 
   583 \item[\ttindexbold{step_tac} $cs$ $i$] is the basic step of the proof
   584   procedure.  The unsafe wrapper tacticals are applied to a tactic that tries
   585   \texttt{safe_tac}, \texttt{inst_step_tac}, or applies an unsafe rule
   586   from~$cs$.
   587 
   588 \item[\ttindexbold{slow_step_tac}] 
   589   resembles \texttt{step_tac}, but allows backtracking between using safe
   590   rules with instantiation (\texttt{inst_step_tac}) and using unsafe rules.
   591   The resulting search space is larger.
   592 \end{ttdescription}
   593 
   594 
   595 \subsection{Other useful tactics}
   596 \index{tactics!for contradiction}
   597 \index{tactics!for Modus Ponens}
   598 \begin{ttbox} 
   599 contr_tac    :             int -> tactic
   600 mp_tac       :             int -> tactic
   601 eq_mp_tac    :             int -> tactic
   602 swap_res_tac : thm list -> int -> tactic
   603 \end{ttbox}
   604 These can be used in the body of a specialized search.
   605 \begin{ttdescription}
   606 \item[\ttindexbold{contr_tac} {\it i}]\index{assumptions!contradictory}
   607   solves subgoal~$i$ by detecting a contradiction among two assumptions of
   608   the form $P$ and~$\neg P$, or fail.  It may instantiate unknowns.  The
   609   tactic can produce multiple outcomes, enumerating all possible
   610   contradictions.
   611 
   612 \item[\ttindexbold{mp_tac} {\it i}] 
   613 is like \texttt{contr_tac}, but also attempts to perform Modus Ponens in
   614 subgoal~$i$.  If there are assumptions $P\imp Q$ and~$P$, then it replaces
   615 $P\imp Q$ by~$Q$.  It may instantiate unknowns.  It fails if it can do
   616 nothing.
   617 
   618 \item[\ttindexbold{eq_mp_tac} {\it i}] 
   619 is like \texttt{mp_tac} {\it i}, but may not instantiate unknowns --- thus, it
   620 is safe.
   621 
   622 \item[\ttindexbold{swap_res_tac} {\it thms} {\it i}] refines subgoal~$i$ of
   623 the proof state using {\it thms}, which should be a list of introduction
   624 rules.  First, it attempts to prove the goal using \texttt{assume_tac} or
   625 \texttt{contr_tac}.  It then attempts to apply each rule in turn, attempting
   626 resolution and also elim-resolution with the swapped form.
   627 \end{ttdescription}
   628 
   629 \subsection{Creating swapped rules}
   630 \begin{ttbox} 
   631 swapify   : thm list -> thm list
   632 joinrules : thm list * thm list -> (bool * thm) list
   633 \end{ttbox}
   634 \begin{ttdescription}
   635 \item[\ttindexbold{swapify} {\it thms}] returns a list consisting of the
   636 swapped versions of~{\it thms}, regarded as introduction rules.
   637 
   638 \item[\ttindexbold{joinrules} ({\it intrs}, {\it elims})]
   639 joins introduction rules, their swapped versions, and elimination rules for
   640 use with \ttindex{biresolve_tac}.  Each rule is paired with~\texttt{false}
   641 (indicating ordinary resolution) or~\texttt{true} (indicating
   642 elim-resolution).
   643 \end{ttdescription}
   644 
   645 
   646 \section{Setting up the classical reasoner}\label{sec:classical-setup}
   647 \index{classical reasoner!setting up}
   648 Isabelle's classical object-logics, including \texttt{FOL} and \texttt{HOL}, 
   649 have the classical reasoner already set up.  
   650 When defining a new classical logic, you should set up the reasoner yourself.  
   651 It consists of the \ML{} functor \ttindex{ClassicalFun}, which takes the 
   652 argument signature \texttt{CLASSICAL_DATA}:
   653 \begin{ttbox} 
   654 signature CLASSICAL_DATA =
   655   sig
   656   val mp             : thm
   657   val not_elim       : thm
   658   val swap           : thm
   659   val sizef          : thm -> int
   660   val hyp_subst_tacs : (int -> tactic) list
   661   end;
   662 \end{ttbox}
   663 Thus, the functor requires the following items:
   664 \begin{ttdescription}
   665 \item[\tdxbold{mp}] should be the Modus Ponens rule
   666 $\List{\Var{P}\imp\Var{Q};\; \Var{P}} \Imp \Var{Q}$.
   667 
   668 \item[\tdxbold{not_elim}] should be the contradiction rule
   669 $\List{\neg\Var{P};\; \Var{P}} \Imp \Var{R}$.
   670 
   671 \item[\tdxbold{swap}] should be the swap rule
   672 $\List{\neg \Var{P}; \; \neg \Var{R}\Imp \Var{P}} \Imp \Var{R}$.
   673 
   674 \item[\ttindexbold{sizef}] is the heuristic function used for best-first
   675 search.  It should estimate the size of the remaining subgoals.  A good
   676 heuristic function is \ttindex{size_of_thm}, which measures the size of the
   677 proof state.  Another size function might ignore certain subgoals (say,
   678 those concerned with type-checking).  A heuristic function might simply
   679 count the subgoals.
   680 
   681 \item[\ttindexbold{hyp_subst_tacs}] is a list of tactics for substitution in
   682 the hypotheses, typically created by \ttindex{HypsubstFun} (see
   683 Chapter~\ref{substitution}).  This list can, of course, be empty.  The
   684 tactics are assumed to be safe!
   685 \end{ttdescription}
   686 The functor is not at all sensitive to the formalization of the
   687 object-logic.  It does not even examine the rules, but merely applies
   688 them according to its fixed strategy.  The functor resides in {\tt
   689   Provers/classical.ML} in the Isabelle sources.
   690 
   691 \index{classical reasoner|)}
   692 
   693 %%% Local Variables: 
   694 %%% mode: latex
   695 %%% TeX-master: "ref"
   696 %%% End: